Contents

Description of CHPV and GV

Introduction
Analogy
Weightings
Voting
Counting
Outcomes
Party-List
Summary

Evaluations of CHPV and GV

Ranked Ballot

Introduction (RB)
General Criteria
Majority Criteria
Clones & Teaming
Teaming Thresholds
Summary (RB)

Party-List

Introduction (PL)
Diagrams & Maps
CHPV Maps
Optimality
Party Cloning
Proportionality
Summary (PL)

Comparisons of CHPV with other voting systems

Single-Winner

Introduction (SW)
Plurality (FPTP)
Borda Count
Geometric Voting
Positional Voting
Condorcet Methods
AV (IRV)
Plur. Rule Methods
Summary (SW)

Multiple-Winner

Introduction (MW)
STV
Party-List
PL ~ Hare
PL ~ Droop
~ Maps Opt PC Pro
PL ~ D'Hondt
~ Maps Opt PC Pro
PL ~ Sainte-Laguë
~ Maps Opt PC Pro
Mixed Member Sys
Summary (MW)

Conclusions

Ranked Ballot CHPV
Party-List CHPV

General

Table of Contents

Map Construction

Table of Contents

Mathematical Proofs

Table of Contents
Notation & Formats

Valid XHTML 1.0 Strict

Valid CSS

Home About Description Evaluations(RB) Evaluations(PL) Comparisons(SW) Comparisons(MW) Conclusions General Maps Proofs
Home About Description Evaluations(RB) Evaluations(PL) Comparisons(SW) Comparisons(MW) Conclusions General Maps Proofs
Home > Proofs > Majority Criteria > EM1
Last Revision: New on 25 Aug 2012

Mathematical Proofs: Majority and Related Criteria

Proof EM1: Majority Threshold as a function of Common Ratio

Scenario: Candidate A has at least one half of all the first preferences; the proportion of all such ballots cast being m (where 1/2 ≤ m ≤ 1). Candidate B has all the remaining first preferences; this proportion therefore being 1 - m. Candidate B also has the second preference of every voter that ranked A as their first preference; the proportion hence being m. This scenario provides B with the best opportunity to beat A despite A having more first preferences than B.

The worst case for A (and the best for B) is extended when those voters who awarded B their first preference truncate their ballot before ranking A so awarding A a zero weighting.

Using standard notation and formats, the profile for this first election scenario is given below.

Alternatively, in an unlimited field of candidates (N → ∞), instead of truncation these first preference B voters could award their lowest preference to A as its weighting is vanishingly small (wN → 0).

Using standard notation and formats, the profile for this second election scenario is given below.

The standard GV weightings are used here to determine the tallies for candidates A and B. In both scenarios, candidate A receives zero weightings from B supporters. The tallies for the other candidates are irrelevant as none of them can possibly beat B. For candidate A to avoid being beaten by B, the tally for A (TA) must be greater than or equal to the tally for B (TB). By evaluating these tallies, the required majority of first preferences (m) as a function of the common ratio (r) can be derived; as shown below.

Proof EM1

The majority threshold is therefore m = 1/(2 - r) and values of m exceeding this threshold guarantee victory to candidate A.


Return to main text > Evaluations: Majority Criteria 1

Refer to > Mathematical Proofs: Table of Contents